The Essence of Evil
by David Livingstone Smith
In March 1945, Leatherneck Magazine, an official organ of
the United States Marine Corps, published a brief, ostensibly humorous article
describing a parasite named Louseous Japanicas. It included an illustration of
a grotesque creature with stereotypically Japanese features. The accompanying
text tells us that:
To the Marine Corps, especially trained in combating this
type of pestilence, was assigned the gigantic task of extermination… Flame
throwers, mortars, grenades and bayonets have proven to be an effective remedy.
But before a complete cure may be effected the origin of the plague, the
breeding grounds around the Tokyo area, must be completely annihilated.
Later that same month, US warplanes dropped 2,000 tons of
incendiary bombs on the city of Tokyo. The stench of burning flesh was so
intense that fighter pilots reached for their oxygen masks. Over the next five
months, at least half a million Japanese men, women and children were, in the
words of the US Air Force General Curtis LeMay, ‘scorched and boiled and baked
to death’ in the firebombing of 67 Japanese cities. And then there were
Hiroshima and Nagasaki…
Only a few years earlier in Germany, Jews were labelled
Untermenschen (subhumans) and were likened to vermin, maggots and
disease-transmitting parasites. Half a century later in Rwanda, Hutu
génocidaires referred to their Tutsi quarry as cockroaches and snakes. This
year, the Israeli Prime Minister Benjamin Netanyahu characterised the Palestinian
killers of three abducted Jewish teenagers as predatory beasts (an epithet that
he did not apply to the Jewish extremists who burned a Palestinian boy alive in
retribution). ‘They were kidnapped and murdered in cold blood by animals,’ he
said. ‘Hamas is responsible and Hamas will pay.’
What is the common element in all these stories? It is, of
course, the phenomenon of dehumanisation. But this is neither recent nor
peculiar to Western civilisation. We find it in the writings from the ancient
civilisations of Egypt, Mesopotamia, Greece and China, and in indigenous
cultures all over the planet. At all these times and in all these places, it
has promoted violence and oppression. And so it would seem to be a matter of
considerable urgency to understand exactly what goes on when people dehumanise
one another. Yet we still know remarkably little about it.
Here’s what we can say. The term ‘dehumanisation’ has
acquired a variety of meanings since its introduction in the early 19th
century. Some people think of it as a derogatory language-game: the rhetorical
practice of likening human beings to non-human animals or inanimate objects.
Others understand it as the act of degrading others by subjecting them to
cruelties or indignities. Still others believe that we dehumanise people by
denying them subjectivity, individuality, agency or other quintessentially
human characteristics. My focus is on a different conception of dehumanisation
– a deeper one that typically underpins all the others. We dehumanise other
people when we conceive of them as subhuman creatures. Dehumanisers do not
think of their victims as subhuman in some merely metaphorical or analogical
sense. They think of them as actually subhuman. The Nazis didn’t just call Jews
vermin. They quite literally conceived of them as vermin in human form.
Look at how European settlers thought about the Africans
whom they enslaved. As the US historian of slavery David Brion Davis remarks:
‘It was this extreme form of dehumanisation – a process mostly confined to the
treatment of slaves and the perceptions of whites – that severed ties of human
identity and empathy and made slavery possible.’ The writings of Morgan Godwyn,
a 17th-century Anglican clergyman who campaigned relentlessly for the civil
rights of Africans and Native Americans, throw considerable light on how
English colonists thought about their putatively subhuman slaves. In The
Negro’s and Indians Advocate (1680), he wrote that he had been told ‘privately
(and as it were in the dark)… That the Negros, though in their Figure they
carry some resemblances of Manhood, yet are indeed no Men.’ ‘They are,’ he
continued, ‘Unman’d and Unsoul’d; accounted and even ranked with Brutes’ –
‘Creatures destitute of Souls, to be ranked among Brute Beasts, and treated
accordingly.’ This pattern of thinking
has been reproduced with spine-chilling fidelity across time and space, and
from one historical epoch to the next
It is instructive to compare Godwyn’s account with a much
more recent example of dehumanising discourse. Der Untermensch (‘the subhuman’)
was a pamphlet published in 1942 under the editorial direction of Heinrich
Himmler, the Nazi responsible for setting up the concentration camps, and it
presented Jews as ravenous subhuman predators. ‘Not all of those who appear
human are in fact so,’ the authors warned. Jews were not human beings, but
rather ‘beasts in human appearance’ that were ‘lower on the spiritual and
psychological scale than any animal’.
Although separated by centuries, these two mindsets – the
colonial and the Nazi – are astonishingly similar. Both claim that the human
appearance of certain groups belies their true nature. So, apparently, while
Africans and Jews display all of the outward marks of humanity, deep down,
where it really matters, they lack that special something that makes one human;
their humanity is only skin-deep, concealing a subhuman core. This pattern of
thinking has been reproduced with spine-chilling fidelity across time and
space, from culture to culture, and from one historical epoch to the next. Its
sheer pervasiveness suggests that it reflects something fundamental about the
human mind.
Investigations into the phenomenon of psychological
essentialism cast a powerful light on the psychological wellsprings of
dehumanisation. The philosophical doctrine of essentialism (the belief that
there are essences) has a lengthy history stretching back at least as far as
Plato and Aristotle. The essence of a thing is supposed to be whatever property
or properties it has that make it the kind of thing it is. Consider a wedding
band fashioned from pure gold. What makes it the case that this chunk of matter
is a piece of gold? Philosophers have pointed to the fact that it possesses the
essence of gold. Its essence lies in its microphysical structure: a substance
counts as gold if and only if the atoms from which it is composed have
precisely 79 protons in their nuclei. It’s because every atom of gold has 79
protons, and every atom with 79 protons is an atom of gold, that the atomic
number 79 is the essence of gold.
The Reverend Godwyn’s contemporary, the English philosopher
John Locke, was an important contributor to the theory of essences. He
distinguished between real essences and merely nominal ones. Nominal essences
are ordinary, commonsensical concepts of kinds of things, whereas real essences
are deep, unobservable properties that make a thing a member of a kind. The
real essence of gold, hidden in its atomic structure, is inaccessible to casual
observation, but its merely nominal essence is simply a list of the descriptors
that we ordinarily associate with gold (heavy, yellow, precious ductile metal,
etc). ‘Essence may be taken for the very being of any thing, whereby it is,
what it is,’ wrote Locke in 1689, ‘And thus the real internal, but generally in
Substances, unknown Constitution of Things, whereon their discoverable
Qualities depend, may be called their Essence’. He warned, however, that ‘if
you demand what those real essences are, it is plain men are ignorant and know
them not … and yet, though we know nothing of these real essences, there is
nothing more ordinary than that men should attribute the sorts of things to
such essences’.
What is it that
makes a porcupine? It’s not its quilly appearance. A mutant porcupine without
quills is a still a porcupine
Nearly 300 years after Locke had penned those words, the
notion of real essences got up from the philosopher’s armchair and entered the
laboratory. In 1989, the psychologists Douglas Medin and Andrew Ortony, both at
Northwest University in Illinois, coined the term ‘psychological essentialism’
to denote our pervasive and seemingly irrepressible tendency to essentialise
categories of things. Since then, researchers have accumulated a sizeable body
of empirical evidence that humans are natural-born essentialists. We are
disposed to think of the world as carved up into discrete kinds of things, each
of which has a real essence.
Biological species are a good example. People the world over
segment the animal kingdom into species. But what makes an animal a member of a
certain species? What is it that makes a certain creature a porcupine? It’s
certainly not its quilly appearance. A mutant porcupine without quills is a
still a porcupine. Psychologists and cognitive anthropologists have shown that
people tend to believe tacitly (and sometimes explicitly) that what makes an
animal a member of a certain species is not its outward appearance but rather
some deep fact about it – in this case, the porcupine essence – even though we
might have no coherent idea of what that essence consists in (recall Locke’s
insight that ‘it is plain men are ignorant and know them not’).
To appreciate how effortlessly we bisect the world into
outward appearance and inner reality, one need only consider cinematic
portrayals of vampires. Under most circumstances, vampires are
indistinguishable from genuine human beings. You might strike up a conversation
with one in a bar without having any suspicions at all, until the moment she
sinks her fangs into your throat. Cinematic vampires are ersatz humans because
they lack the inner spark that that all human beings supposedly share. I doubt
that many people find this difficult to wrap their minds around. Likewise, the
first audiences of A Midsummer Night’s Dream had no trouble understanding that
though Bottom’s head looked like that of a donkey, he was really a human being
‘on the inside’, the donkeyish appearance concealing the human essence.
The phenomenon of psychological essentialism explains how we
are able to think of others as non-human creatures despite all appearances. But
it gives us no purchase on the crucial issue of subhumanity. When we dehumanise
others, we do not simply regard them as non-human. We regard them as less than
human. Where does that come from?
Read the rest of this article here:
No comments:
Post a Comment
Please leave a comment.