The Ministry of Truth
by Elijah Millgram
Orwell taught us to fear technocratic jargon that doesn’t
let us say what we mean. But that is language at its best…Everyone remembers
Newspeak, the straitjacketed version of English from George Orwell’s novel 1984
(1949). In that dystopia, Newspeak was a language designed by ideological
technicians to make politically incorrect thoughts literally inexpressible.
Fewer people know that Orwell also worried about the poverty of our ordinary,
unregimented vocabulary. Too often, he believed, we lack the words to say
exactly what we mean, and so we say something else, something in the general
neighbourhood, usually a lot less nuanced than what we had in mind; for
example, he observed that ‘all likes and dislikes, all aesthetic feeling, all
notions of right and wrong… spring from feelings which are generally admitted
to be subtler than words’. His solution was ‘to invent new words as
deliberately as we would invent new parts for a motor-car engine’. This, he
suggested in an essay titled ‘New Words’ (1940), might be the occupation of
‘several thousands of… people.’ Now, I don’t have anything against the
invention of new words when it’s appropriate. But Orwell was badly mistaken,
and not just for ignoring the fact that English already picks up new words on a
daily basis. His reasons for wanting that extra expressive power are,
uncharacteristically, poorly thought-out. Language just doesn’t work in the way
that either 1984’s Ministry of Truth or the more benign bureau of verbal inventors
in ‘New Words’ presume. And understanding why that is will put us in a position
to explain a lot of what goes under the heading of metaphysics.
Imagine you really did have a repertoire of concepts and
names that allowed you to say exactly what you meant, pretty much whatever you
noticed, or whatever occurred to you. Adrienne Lehrer, a linguist at the
University of Arizona, wrote Wine and Conversation (2009), a book about wine
vocabulary: ‘earthy’, ‘full-bodied’, ‘flowery’, ‘cloying’, ‘disciplined’,
‘mossy’, and so on. Many, many such adjectives turn up in wine commentary,
though evidently not enough of them to live up to Orwell’s ideal. Imagine really
having precise terms for all those flavour notes. Orwell was especially worried
about capturing our inner lives, so imagine also having words for the
day-to-day events that remind you of particular experiences that only you have
undergone. Feeling a little swamped? It’s not simply that your mind would be
submerged in conceptual clutter; it’s not just that it wouldn’t be possible to
learn most of these words, or to communicate with them. In fact, Lehrer found
that people don’t manage to communicate very well with their wine vocabularies;
if subjects are asked to pick a wine out of a lineup on the basis of someone
else’s description of it, they mostly can’t do it. Presumably this sort of talk
isn’t really about communication, but it’s also something of an exception.
For the most part, our repertoire of concepts and labels for
individuals is important because we use it in our reasoning. Descriptions are
useful in that we can draw conclusions from them. In the most basic case, you
would use a rule: when certain conditions are met (for example, when you’re
making the American chef Deborah Madison’s mashed potatoes and turnips),
certain implications follow (an appropriate pairing would be a Sancerre in the
summer, or a Cabernet Franc from the Loire in fall or winter). Your
ever-so-precise mot juste might capture exactly what you see or feel but, if
there’s no inference you can fit it to, then there’s nothing you can do with
it. Descriptions that you can’t fold into your reasoning are useless. The thing
is, the useful ones don’t come easy. Back in the 18th century, the philosopher
David Hume thought that we were mostly led from one belief to another by
causes, and he thought we learned that As cause Bs by seeing lots of As
followed by lots of Bs. That’s somewhat oversimplified, but it’ll do as a
stand-in. It would mean that in order to add a causal connection to your
intellectual repertoire, somebody or other would have to take the time to
observe all those As and Bs. If we do this systematically, that’s science.
(It’s not always science: if we do it with recipes, it’s kitchen testing.) Now,
science takes time and money, and as the US Congress keeps reminding the
National Science Foundation and NASA, there’s only so much to go around. The
point generalises: those inferential connections are expensive, and we can
afford only so many of them. So if you want to think effectively, you have to
be selective. You have to confine your descriptions of the world around you, of
your inner life and all the rest of it, to the descriptions that someone has
invested in, doing what was needed to embed them in a network of usable
inferential links. We can’t avoid cutting intellectual corners, forcing our
experience to fit our language and then squinting to see whether the
conclusions we draw still standMost of the time, you don’t have much of a say
in where those investments are made, and so you end up with a descriptive
vocabulary that doesn’t quite fit what you want to think about, or tell other
people about. But, in those cases, the right thing to do is exactly what Orwell
doesn’t like. Go ahead, use words that misdescribe whatever it is. Choose terms
that let you draw conclusions. But (and maybe this would improve matters by his
lights) be upfront about what you’re doing. Tag what you said as pretty much
true, or almost entirely true, or true enough, or technically true, or maybe
just good enough for government work. Or use a hedge like the one from a few
lines back: somewhat oversimplified, but it’ll do as a stand-in. Maybe Orwell
was right that we need to invent more words. I do think we could use more
qualifiers such as these.
Philosophers in the English-speaking world for the most part
think of truth as an all-or-nothing matter. (Here’s a typical expression of
this attitude, borrowed from Charles Travis’ Unshadowed Thought (2000):
‘‘Approximately’, like ‘basically’, is a polite negation. If what I say is
(only) approximately true, then it is, strictly speaking, false.’) I think
otherwise. It’s actually more important to be able to register how something
you said was partways true than it is to announce that something is simply
true. (Most of the time when you do that, it’s repetition for emphasis.) We
can’t avoid cutting intellectual corners, forcing our experience to fit our
language and then squinting to see whether the conclusions we draw still stand.
In other words, we’re in the business of using approximations and
idealisations. In that case, it’s natural to look for recipes – that is,
routinised ways of generating those self-aware misdescriptions, preferably ones
that you can apply in a great many cases. If you’ve taken an introductory
physics class where the problem sets seemed to assume that the world was made
of point masses and rigid bodies and frictionless planes, or if you took intro
econ where markets were populated by perfectly rational and informed buyers and
sellers, you’ve encountered recipes like that. But these aren’t just tricks of
the trade in one scientific discipline or another. We have a great many recipes
for misdescription that work similarly in everyday life. Often we’re so used to
them that we don’t even notice how they get put to work.
Aristotle came up with a simplifying technique of this sort,
one that has made its way into the standard intellectual toolkit that everybody
picks up as a child. I’m sure you don’t need reminding that people can look
very different from one another, and that this is doubly the case when they’re
at different life stages. It would be very tricky to take account of all that
variation; a nine-pound baby and a 270-pound football player have to be handled
very differently on many occasions, for instance when you’re selling them plane
tickets, and you’d think they might count differently. Shouldn’t the football
player, who takes up two seats, count for two, and the infant on a lap for some
fraction? But Aristotle’s descriptive recipe lets us say that if you’re a human
being, you’re exactly one human. When I was born, I was one human, and when I
was big enough to try out for the team, I was one human; if I gain a few
pounds, I don’t clock in at 1.03 humans, and if I lose a few, I don’t become
merely 0.94 of a person.
This is a good idea for all sorts of purposes. It makes our
world much more straightforward, in that it lets us just count off people – but
not just people: also cats and so on – without worrying about those extra
pounds. It’s also metaphysics. We translate Aristotle’s word for these
individual, countable beings as ‘substances’, and philosophers generally agree
that Aristotle’s doctrine of substance is metaphysics. Maybe it’s even the
paradigm of metaphysics. But I’m suggesting that most metaphysics, not just
Aristotle’s, consists of such recipes, formulae for simplifying your
descriptions and making your thinking more straightforward. Metaphysics is
intellectual ergonomics. It’s unusual to hear philosophers agree to that last
part. In the main, they take their job as metaphysicians to be arguing over
whether, say, Aristotelian substances really exist. They tie themselves up in
knots worrying about what persons really are. But maybe that’s because
personhood is an idealisation. The properly Orwellian question here is the same
one we would ask about the idealised point masses of physics or the perfect
markets of economic theory: should we stick with our Aristotelian Newspeak and
use that to misdescribe our surroundings? Or is it getting in our way? Is our
present situation a good occasion to modify it or replace it with something
else?
Even if all that sounds pretty good, there’s a cost to
acknowledge. Orwell went to fight in the Spanish Civil War, and came back
deeply disturbed by how the press subordinated its reportage to one or another
party line. And, he noticed, it wasn’t just the journalists and publishers.
There were a great many alleged human rights violations, and almost everyone
seemed to believe that one or another of them had taken place only if it suited
their party’s tactical needs. Or rather, they only ‘believed’ it had because,
the moment it was convenient, those beliefs would turn on a dime – even when
they were about what were very clearly matters of fact, not decisions or
policies. Orwell turned these observations into the basis for 1984’s
doublethink.
Doublethink isn’t just something we have to cope with in
politics. It is the price of metaphysics, and metaphysics – if what I’ve told
you so far comes close enough to being right – is everywhere. So it seems we have
a choice between two kinds of doublethink. If you’re thinking with the help of
useful idealisations such as these, then the world doesn’t really match your
descriptions of it. Lose track of that fact, come to believe that your
metaphysics are just true, and you’ll have to develop a selective blindness –
in both your intellectual and your day-to-day lives – to what’s actually going
on around you. It will be like the myopia of the left- and right-wingers of
Orwell’s own day, or the perversely oblivious characters in 1984. The economist
who still insists that people really are economically rational agents displays
a familiar contemporary version of that blindness. But since we all have to get
along in a world that doesn’t work quite as our idealised misdescriptions say
it ought to, we will somehow manage both to see things and not to see them. Getting
by in this way runs the risk of looking (and maybe not just looking) dishonest.
And with this dishonesty there might come a certain guilty pleasure. It’s a little
reminiscent of 1950s utopian sci-fi, namely, the thrill of imagining that you
live in a much more orderly, understandable world than we really do.
I don’t think we can do without metaphysics, understood as
intellectual ergonomics: the world is far too messy a placeThe alternative to
this kind of fantastical dogmatism is always to accompany what you announce
with hedges. You see that a conclusion follows from your idealised description,
and you remind yourself not to draw it on this occasion. You warn other people
that what you just told them is only roughly true, and to watch out for the
exceptions. You’re honest, but only because you’re always attaching those
reminders that you don’t exactly mean whatever it was you just said. I don’t
think the choice is clean, and sometimes there are ways around it. For example,
misdescriptions can be a bit like self-fulfilling prophecies. Emotional
investment sometimes follows those inferential investments; as you get used to
thinking and talking with other people using some set of crisply articulated
concepts, your interest can gradually shift to the common ground. A good number
of philosophers originally took up the subject because they had what some
people call existential concerns – that is, they were worried about the meaning
of life. But in the field, there hasn’t been a lot of research investment in
that concept. The nearest thing is probably value theory, or maybe metaethics.
And so, decades later, those philosophers often find that they care about
issues in value theory and metaethics, and have entirely forgotten that they
originally wanted to know about the meaning of life.
Perhaps that sounds a bit iffy. Haven’t those philosophers
lost their way? Probably, but not everyone who lives through these shifts of
interest necessarily has. Sometimes it really is important that what you reason
about and what you care about are exactly the same things. And sometimes you
can get them to match up by gradually changing what you care about. Going back
to our earlier illustration, for certain purposes anyway, shouldn’t you care
about, precisely, people, and not so much about the messy real-world things we
all are, which are only approximately people? I don’t think we can do without
metaphysics, understood as the kind of intellectual ergonomics I’ve just
described; the world is far too messy a place. And mostly we don’t want to
quietly forget about the bits and pieces of the mess that matter to us. So
we’re going to have to live with doublethink. The only question is, which kind?
I can feel the temptations of the first option. Wouldn’t it
be so orderly to live in the British philosopher Timothy Williamson’s world,
where the vague concepts all come with clean, sharp boundaries? (It’s just that
we’ll never know where they are.) Wouldn’t it be reassuring to live in the
world of the American philosophers W V O Quine and Donald Davidson, where
people are never illogical, and are mostly right about most things? (If it
seems otherwise, you must be mistranslating them.) Maybe it’s just me, but I
prefer honest doublethink, where you’re upfront with yourself and with other
people about your misrepresentations. The other sort – where you tell yourself
that the world is as you say, but then somehow simultaneously cope with and
ignore the ways it isn’t – is probably the norm in many walks of life: it
certainly is in the world of professional philosophy. But I don’t want, as
Orwell put it, ‘to know and not to know, to be conscious of complete
truthfulness while telling carefully constructed lies’ – no doubt in part for
the reasons that his readers were horrified at such descriptions of the cynical
apparatchiks of 1984.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Please leave a comment.